BIAS IN MEDICAL RESEARCH ARTICLE ANALYSIS

Writing Assignment

Following this instruction sheet is a very powerful analysis of how bias and statistical manipulation has

resulted in flawed medical studies. (Hint: Do not attempt to understand the statistics he presents. Focus on

the concepts the author is trying to address). Read the article and write up a 1-2 page report answering the following questions:

1. Write an overview or brief summary of the article. Indicate your assessment of what the

article is about and the major findings of the article.

2. What is the author’s thesis or main point expressed in this article? Why does he believe that

most medical research is flawed?

3. How does this article relate to what you have learned in class about experimental research?

4. Before reading this article, what were your beliefs and attitudes toward the quality and

accuracy of research studies findings published in professional journals? How has reading this

article changed, if at all, your beliefs and attitudes toward published research findings?

5. What does the author believe can be done to improve the quality and objectivity of research?

Do you agree or disagree with his recommendations? Explain.

FORMAT: 1-2 pages, 1″ margins, double spaced, normal font. All papers must be neatly typed and proofread.

DUE DATE: Last Day of the Final Exam, 11:59 pm

GRADING: This extra credit assignment is worth 10 points. Points will be reduced for spelling, grammar, etc., and for lack of content.

PLoS Medicine | www.plosmedicine.org 697 August 2005 | Volume 2 | Issue 8 | e124

sometimes refuted by subsequent

Open access, freely available online

Essay

Why Most Published Research Findings Are False John P. A. Ioannidis

P

ublished research findings are

factors that influence this problem and

some corollaries thereof.

Modeling the Framework for False Positive Findings

Several methodologists have

pointed out [9–11] that the high

rate of nonreplication (lack of

confirmation) of research discoveries

is a consequence of the convenient,

yet ill-founded strategy of claiming

conclusive research findings solely on

the basis of a single study assessed by

formal statistical significance, typically

for a p-value less than 0.05. Research is not most appropriately represented

and summarized by p-values, but, unfortunately, there is a widespread

notion that medical research articles

It can be proven that most claimed research findings are false.

should be interpreted based only on

p-values. Research findings are defined

here as any relationship reaching

formal statistical significance, e.g.,

effective interventions, informative

predictors, risk factors, or associations.

“Negative” research is also very useful.

“Negative” is actually a misnomer, and

the misinterpretation is widespread.

among those tested in the field. R

is characteristic of the field and can

vary a lot depending on whether the

field targets highly likely relationships

or searches for only one or a few

true relationships among thousands

and millions of hypotheses that may

be postulated. Let us also consider,

for computational simplicity,

circumscribed fields where either there

is only one true relationship (among

many that can be hypothesized) or

the power is similar to find any of the

several existing true relationships. The

pre-study probability of a relationship

being true is R⁄(R + 1). The probability of a study finding a true relationship

reflects the power 1 − β (one minus

the Type II error rate). The probability

of claiming a relationship when none

truly exists reflects the Type I error

rate, α. Assuming that c relationships

are being probed in the field, the

expected values of the 2 × 2 table are

given in Table 1. After a research

finding has been claimed based on

achieving formal statistical significance,

the post-study probability that it is true

is the positive predictive value, PPV.

The PPV is also the complementary

probability of what Wacholder et al.

have called the false positive report

probability [10]. According to the 2

× 2 table, one gets PPV = (1 − β)R⁄(R − βR + α). A research finding is thus

evidence, with ensuing confusion and

disappointment. Refutation and

controversy is seen across the range of

research designs, from clinical trials

and traditional epidemiological studies

[1–3] to the most modern molecular

research [4,5]. There is increasing

concern that in modern research, false

findings may be the majority or even

the vast majority of published research

claims [6–8]. However, this should

not be surprising. It can be proven

that most claimed research findings

are false. Here I will examine the key

The Essay section contains opinion pieces on topics

of broad interest to a general medical audience.

relationships that investigators claim

exist, rather than null findings.

As has been shown previously, the

probability that a research finding

is indeed true depends on the prior

probability of it being true (before

doing the study), the statistical power

of the study, and the level of statistical

significance [10,11]. Consider a 2 × 2

table in which research findings are

compared against the gold standard

of true relationships in a scientific

field. In a research field both true and

false hypotheses can be made about

the presence of relationships. Let R

be the ratio of the number of “true

relationships” to “no relationships”

Citation: Ioannidis JPA (2005) W hy most published research findings are false. PLoS Med 2(8): e124.

Copyright: © 2005 John P. A. Ioannidis. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original

work is properly cited.

Abbreviation: PPV, positive predictive value

John P. A. Ioannidis is in the Department of Hygiene

and Epidemiology, University of Ioannina School of Medicine, Ioannina, Greece, and Institute for Clinical Research and Health Policy Studies, Department of Medicine, Tufts-New England Medical Center, Tufts University School of Medicine, Boston, Massachusetts, United States of America. E-mail: [email protected]

Competing Interests: The author has declared that no competing interests exist.

Summary

There is increasing concern that most

current published research findings are

false. The probability that a research claim

is true may depend on study power and

bias, the number of other studies on the

same question, and, importantly, the ratio

of true to no relationships among the

relationships probed in each scientific

field. In this framework, a research finding

is less likely to be true when the studies

conducted in a field are smaller; when

effect sizes are smaller; when there is a

greater number and lesser preselection

of tested relationships; where there is

greater flexibility in designs, definitions,

outcomes, and analytical modes; when

there is greater financial and other

interest and prejudice; and when more

teams are involved in a scientific field

in chase of statistical significance.

Simulations show that for most study

designs and settings, it is more likely for

a research claim to be false than true.

Moreover, for many current scientific

fields, claimed research findings may

often be simply accurate measures of the

prevailing bias. In this essay, I discuss the

implications of these problems for the

conduct and interpretation of research.

However, here we will target

http://www.plosmedicine.org/
mailto:[email protected]
PLoS Medicine | www.plosmedicine.org 698 August 2005 | Volume 2 | Issue 8 | e124

Table 1. Research Findings and True Relationships same question, claims a statistically significant research finding is easy to Research Finding

True Relationship

Yes No Total estimate. For n independent studies of equal power, the 2 × 2 table is shown in

Yes c(1 − β)R/(R + 1) cα/(R + 1) c(R + α − βR)/(R + 1)

No cβR/(R + 1) c(1 − α)/(R + 1) c(1 − α + βR)/(R + 1)

Total cR/(R + 1) c/(R + 1) c

Table 3: PPV = R(1 − βn)⁄(R + 1 − [1 − α]n − Rβn) (not considering bias). With increasing number of independent

studies, PPV tends to decrease, unless DOI: 10.1371/journal.pmed.0020124.t001

more likely true than false if (1 − β)R > α. Since usually the vast majority of

investigators depend on α = 0.05, this

means that a research finding is more

likely true than false if (1 − β)R > 0.05.

What is less well appreciated is

that bias and the extent of repeated

independent testing by different teams

of investigators around the globe may

further distort this picture and may

lead to even smaller probabilities of the

research findings being indeed true.

We will try to model these two factors in

the context of similar 2 × 2 tables.

Bias

First, let us define bias as the

combination of various design, data,

analysis, and presentation factors that

tend to produce research findings

when they should not be produced.

Let u be the proportion of probed

analyses that would not have been

“research findings,” but nevertheless

end up presented and reported as

such, because of bias. Bias should not

be confused with chance variability

that causes some findings to be false by

chance even though the study design,

data, analysis, and presentation are

perfect. Bias can entail manipulation

in the analysis or reporting of findings.

Selective or distorted reporting is a

typical form of such bias. We may

assume that u does not depend on

whether a true relationship exists or not. This is not an unreasonable

assumption, since typically it is

impossible to know which relationships

are indeed true. In the presence of bias

(Table 2), one gets PPV = ([1 − β]R + uβR)⁄(R + α − βR + u − uα + uβR), and PPV decreases with increasing u, unless 1 − β ≤ α, i.e., 1 − β ≤ 0.05 for most

situations. Thus, with increasing bias,

are lost in noise [12], or investigators

use data inefficiently or fail to notice

statistically significant relationships, or

there may be conflicts of interest that

tend to “bury” significant findings [13].

There is no good large-scale empirical

evidence on how frequently such

reverse bias may occur across diverse

research fields. However, it is probably

fair to say that reverse bias is not as

common. Moreover measurement

errors and inefficient use of data are

probably becoming less frequent

problems, since measurement error has

decreased with technological advances

in the molecular era and investigators

are becoming increasingly sophisticated

about their data. Regardless, reverse

bias may be modeled in the same way as

bias above. Also reverse bias should not

be confused with chance variability that

may lead to missing a true relationship

because of chance.

Testing by Several Independent Teams

Several independent teams may be

addressing the same sets of research

questions. As research efforts are

globalized, it is practically the rule

that several research teams, often

dozens of them, may probe the same

or similar questions. Unfortunately, in

some areas, the prevailing mentality

until now has been to focus on

isolated discoveries by single teams

and interpret research experiments

in isolation. An increasing number

of questions have at least one study

claiming a research finding, and

this receives unilateral attention.

The probability that at least one

study, among several done on the

1 − β < α, i.e., typically 1 − β < 0.05. This is shown for different levels of power and for different pre-study odds in Figure 2. For n studies of different power, the term βn is replaced by the product of the terms β i for i = 1 to n, but inferences are similar. Corollaries A practical example is shown in Box 1. Based on the above considerations, one may deduce several interesting corollaries about the probability that a research finding is indeed true. Corollary 1: The smaller the studies conducted in a scientific field, the less likely the research findings are to be true. Small sample size means smaller power and, for all functions above, the PPV for a true research finding decreases as power decreases towards 1 − β = 0.05. Thus, other factors being equal, research findings are more likely true in scientific fields that undertake large studies, such as randomized controlled trials in cardiology (several thousand subjects randomized) [14] than in scientific fields with small studies, such as most research of molecular predictors (sample sizes 100- fold smaller) [15]. Corollary 2: The smaller the effect sizes in a scientific field, the less likely the research findings are to be true. Power is also related to the effect size. Thus research findings are more likely true in scientific fields with large effects, such as the impact of smoking on cancer or cardiovascular disease (relative risks 3–20), than in scientific fields where postulated effects are small, such as genetic risk factors for multigenetic diseases (relative risks 1.1–1.5) [7]. Modern epidemiology is increasingly obliged to target smaller the chances that a research finding Table 2. Research Findings and True Relationships in the Presence of Bias is true diminish considerably. This is shown for different levels of power and for different pre-study odds in Figure 1. Conversely, true research findings may occasionally be annulled because of reverse bias. For example, with large Research True Relationship measurement errors relationships DOI: 10.1371/journal.pmed.0020124.t002 Finding Yes No Total Yes (c[1 − β]R + ucβR)/(R + 1) cα + uc(1 − α)/(R + 1) c(R + α − βR + u − uα + uβR)/(R + 1) No (1 − u)cβR/(R + 1) (1 − u)c(1 − α)/(R + 1) c(1 − u)(1 − α + βR)/(R + 1) Total cR/(R + 1) c/(R + 1) c http://www.plosmedicine.org/ PLoS Medicine | www.plosmedicine.org 699 August 2005 | Volume 2 | Issue 8 | e124 effect sizes [16]. Consequently, the proportion of true research findings is expected to decrease. In the same line of thinking, if the true effect sizes are very small in a scientific field, this field is likely to be plagued by almost ubiquitous false positive claims. For example, if the majority of true genetic or nutritional determinants of complex diseases confer relative risks less than 1.05, genetic or nutritional epidemiology would be largely utopian endeavors. Corollary 3: The greater the number and the lesser the selection of tested relationships in a scientific field, the less likely the research findings are to be true. As shown above, the post-study probability that a finding is true (PPV) depends a lot on the pre-study odds (R). Thus, research findings are more likely true in confirmatory designs, such as large phase III randomized controlled trials, or meta-analyses thereof, than in hypothesis-generating experiments. Fields considered highly informative and creative given the wealth of the assembled and tested information, such as microarrays and other high-throughput discovery- oriented research [4,8,17], should have extremely low PPV. Corollary 4: The greater the flexibility in designs, definitions, outcomes, and analytical modes in a scientific field, the less likely the research findings are to be true. Flexibility increases the potential for transforming what would be “negative” results into “positive” results, i.e., bias, u. For several research designs, e.g., randomized controlled trials [18–20] or meta-analyses [21,22], there have been efforts to standardize their conduct and reporting. Adherence to common standards is likely to increase the proportion of true findings. The same applies to outcomes. True findings may be more common when outcomes are unequivocal and universally agreed (e.g., death) rather than when multifarious outcomes are devised (e.g., scales for schizophrenia outcomes) [23]. Similarly, fields that use commonly agreed, stereotyped analytical methods (e.g., Kaplan- Meier plots and the log-rank test) [24] may yield a larger proportion of true findings than fields where analytical methods are still under experimentation (e.g., artificial intelligence methods) and only “best” results are reported. Regardless, even in the most stringent research designs, bias seems to be a major problem. For example, there is strong evidence that selective outcome reporting, with manipulation of the outcomes and analyses reported, is a common problem even for randomized trails [25]. Simply abolishing selective publication would not make this problem go away. Corollary 5: The greater the financial and other interests and prejudices in a scientific field, the less likely the research findings are to be true. Conflicts of interest and prejudice may increase bias, u. Conflicts of interest are very common in biomedical research [26], and typically they are inadequately and sparsely reported [26,27]. Prejudice may not necessarily have financial roots. Scientists in a given field may be prejudiced purely because of their belief in a scientific theory or commitment to their own findings. Many otherwise seemingly independent, university-based studies may be conducted for no other reason than to give physicians and researchers qualifications for promotion or tenure. Such nonfinancial conflicts may also lead to distorted reported results and interpretations. Prestigious investigators may suppress via the peer review process the appearance and dissemination of findings that refute their findings, thus condemning their field to perpetuate false dogma. Empirical evidence on expert opinion shows that it is extremely unreliable [28]. Corollary 6: The hotter a scientific field (with more scientific teams involved), the less likely the research findings are to be true. DOI: 10.1371/journal.pmed.0020124.g001 Figure 1. PPV (Probability That a Research Finding Is True) as a Function of the Pre-Study Odds for Various Levels of Bias, u Panels correspond to power of 0.20, 0.50, and 0.80. This seemingly paradoxical corollary follows because, as stated above, the PPV of isolated findings decreases when many teams of investigators are involved in the same field. This may explain why we occasionally see major excitement followed rapidly by severe disappointments in fields that draw wide attention. With many teams working on the same field and with massive experimental data being produced, timing is of the essence in beating competition. Thus, each team may prioritize on pursuing and disseminating its most impressive “positive” results. “Negative” results may Table 3. Research Findings and True Relationships in the Presence of Multiple Studies become attractive for dissemination Research True Relationship only if some other team has found a “positive” association on the same question. In that case, it may be attractive to refute a claim made in some prestigious journal. The term Proteus phenomenon has been coined DOI: 10.1371/journal.pmed.0020124.t003 to describe this phenomenon of rapidly Finding Yes No Total Yes cR(1 − βn)/(R + 1) c(1 − [1 − α]n)/(R + 1) c(R + 1 − [1 − α]n − Rβn)/(R + 1) No cRβn/(R + 1) c(1 − α)n/(R + 1) c([1 − α]n + Rβn)/(R + 1) Total cR/(R + 1) c/(R + 1) c http://www.plosmedicine.org/ PLoS Medicine | www.plosmedicine.org 700 August 2005 | Volume 2 | Issue 8 | e124 DOI: 10.1371/journal.pmed.0020124.g002 Figure 2. PPV (Probability That a Research Finding Is True) as a Function of the Pre-Study Odds for Various Numbers of Conducted Studies, n Panels correspond to power of 0.20, 0.50, and 0.80. alternating extreme research claims and extremely opposite refutations [29]. Empirical evidence suggests that this sequence of extreme opposites is very common in molecular genetics [29]. These corollaries consider each factor separately, but these factors often influence each other. For example, investigators working in fields where true effect sizes are perceived to be small may be more likely to perform large studies than investigators working in fields where true effect sizes are perceived to be large. Or prejudice may prevail in a hot scientific field, further undermining the predictive value of its research findings. Highly prejudiced stakeholders may even create a barrier that aborts efforts at obtaining and disseminating opposing results. Conversely, the fact that a field Box 1. An Example: Science at Low Pre-Study Odds Let us assume that a team of investigators performs a whole genome association study to test whether any of 100,000 gene polymorphisms are associated with susceptibility to schizophrenia. Based on what we know about the extent of heritability of the disease, it is reasonable to expect that probably around ten gene polymorphisms among those tested would be truly associated with schizophrenia, with relatively similar odds ratios around 1.3 for the ten or so polymorphisms and with a fairly similar power to identify any of them. Then R = 10/100,000 = 10−4, and the pre-study probability for any polymorphism to be associated with schizophrenia is also R/(R + 1) = 10−4. Let us also suppose that the study has 60% power to find an association with an odds ratio of 1.3 at α = 0.05. Then it can be estimated that if a statistically significant association is found with the p-value barely crossing the 0.05 threshold, the post-study probability that this is true increases about 12-fold compared with the pre-study probability, but it is still only 12 × 10−4. Now let us suppose that the investigators manipulate their design, is hot or has strong invested interests may sometimes promote larger studies and improved standards of research, enhancing the predictive value of its research findings. Or massive discovery- oriented testing may result in such a large yield of significant relationships that investigators have enough to report and search further and thus refrain from data dredging and manipulation. Most Research Findings Are False for Most Research Designs and for Most Fields In the described framework, a PPV exceeding 50% is quite difficult to get. Table 4 provides the results of simulations using the formulas developed for the influence of power, ratio of true to non-true relationships, and bias, for various types of situations that may be characteristic of specific study designs and settings. A finding from a well-conducted, adequately powered randomized controlled trial starting with a 50% pre-study chance that the intervention is effective is analyses, and reporting so as to make more relationships cross the p = 0.05 threshold even though this would not have been crossed with a perfectly adhered to design and analysis and with perfect comprehensive reporting of the results, strictly according to the original study plan. Such manipulation could be done, for example, with serendipitous inclusion or exclusion of certain patients or controls, post hoc subgroup analyses, investigation of genetic contrasts that were not originally specified, changes in the disease or control definitions, and various combinations of selective or distorted reporting of the results. Commercially available“data mining” packages actually are proud of their ability to yield statistically significant results through data dredging. In the presence of bias with u = 0.10, the post- study probability that a research finding is true is only 4.4 × 10−4. Furthermore, even in the absence of any bias, when ten independent research teams perform similar experiments around the world, if one of them finds a formally statistically significant association, the probability that the research finding is true is only 1.5 × 10−4, hardly any higher than the probability we had before any of this extensive research was undertaken! eventually true about 85% of the time. A fairly similar performance is expected of a confirmatory meta-analysis of good-quality randomized trials: potential bias probably increases, but power and pre-test chances are higher compared to a single randomized trial. Conversely, a meta-analytic finding from inconclusive studies where pooling is used to “correct” the low power of single studies, is probably false if R ≤ 1:3. Research findings from underpowered, early-phase clinical trials would be true about one in four times, or even less frequently if bias is present. Epidemiological studies of an exploratory nature perform even worse, especially when underpowered, but even well-powered epidemiological studies may have only a one in five chance being true, if R = 1:10. Finally, in discovery-oriented research with massive testing, where tested relationships exceed true ones 1,000- fold (e.g., 30,000 genes tested, of which 30 may be the true culprits) [30,31], PPV for each claimed relationship is extremely low, even with considerable http://www.plosmedicine.org/ PLoS Medicine | www.plosmedicine.org 0700 August 2005 | Volume 2 | Issue 8 | e124 standardization of laboratory and statistical methods, outcomes, and reporting thereof to minimize bias. Claimed Research Findings May Often Be Simply Accurate Measures of the Prevailing Bias As shown, the majority of modern biomedical research is operating in areas with very low pre- and post- study probability for true findings. Let us suppose that in a research field there are no true findings at all to be discovered. History of science teaches us that scientific endeavor has often in the past wasted effort in fields with absolutely no yield of true scientific information, at least based on our current understanding. In such a “null field,” one would ideally expect all observed effect sizes to vary by chance around the null in the absence of bias. The extent that observed findings deviate from what is expected by chance alone would be simply a pure measure of the prevailing bias. For example, let us suppose that no nutrients or dietary patterns are actually important determinants for the risk of developing a specific tumor. Let us also suppose that the scientific literature has examined 60 nutrients and claims all of them to be related to the risk of developing this tumor with relative risks in the range of 1.2 to 1.4 for the comparison of the upper to lower intake tertiles. Then the claimed effect sizes are simply measuring nothing else but the net bias that has been involved in the generation of this scientific literature. Claimed effect sizes are in fact the most accurate estimates of the net bias. It even follows that between “null fields,” the fields that claim stronger effects (often with accompanying claims of medical or public health importance) are simply those that have sustained the worst biases. For fields with very low PPV, the few true relationships would not distort this overall picture much. Even if a few relationships are true, the shape of the distribution of the observed effects would still yield a clear measure of the biases involved in the field. This concept totally reverses the way we view scientific results. Traditionally, investigators have viewed large and highly significant effects with excitement, as signs of important discoveries. Too large and too highly significant effects may actually be more likely to be signs of large bias in most fields of modern research. They should lead investigators to careful critical thinking about what might have gone wrong with their data, analyses, and results. Of course, investigators working in any field are likely to resist accepting that the whole field in which they have spent their careers is a “null field.” However, other lines of evidence, or advances in technology and experimentation, may lead eventually to the dismantling of a scientific field. Obtaining measures of the net bias in one field may also be useful for obtaining insight into what might be the range of bias operating in other fields where similar analytical methods, technologies, and conflicts may be operating. How Can We Improve the Situation? Is it unavoidable that most research findings are false, or can we improve the situation? A major problem is that it is impossible to know with 100% certainty what the truth is in any research question. In this regard, the pure “gold” standard is unattainable. However, there are several approaches to improve the post-study probability. Better powered evidence, e.g., large studies or low-bias meta-analyses, may help, as it comes closer to the unknown “gold” standard. However, large studies may still have biases and these should be acknowledged and avoided. Moreover, large-scale evidence is impossible to obtain for all of the millions and trillions of research questions posed in current research. Large-scale evidence should be targeted for research questions where the pre-study probability is already considerably high, so that a significant Table 4. PPV of Research Findings for Various Combinations of Power (1 − β), Ratio of True to Not-True Relationships (R), and Bias (u) 1 − β R u Practical Example PPV research finding will lead to a post-test probability that would be considered quite definitive. Large-scale evidence is also particularly indicated when it can 0.80 1:1 0.10 Adequately powered RCT with little bias and 1:1 pre-study odds 0.85 test major concepts rather than narrow, specific questions. A negative finding 0.95 2:1 0.30 Confirmatory meta-analysis of good- 0.85 quality RCTs can then refute not only a specific proposed claim, but a whole field or 0.80 1:3 0.40 Meta-analysis of small inconclusive studies 0.20 1:5 0.20 Underpowered, but well-performed phase I/II RCT 0.20 1:5 0.80 Underpowered, poorly performed phase I/II RCT 0.80 1:10 0.30 Adequately powered exploratory research with massive testing 0.20 1:1,000 0.20 As in previous example, but with more limited bias (more standardized) 0.41 0.23 0.17 0.20 0.0015 considerable portion thereof. Selecting the performance of large-scale studies based on narrow-minded criteria, such as the marketing promotion of a specific drug, is largely wasted research. Moreover, one should be cautious that extremely large studies may be more likely to find a formally statistical significant difference for a trivial effect that is not really meaningfully different from the null [32–34]. Second, most research questions are addressed by many teams, and it is misleading to emphasize the The estimated PPVs (positive predictive values) are derived assuming α = 0.05 for a single study. RCT, randomized controlled trial. DOI: 10.1371/journal.pmed.0020124.t004 statistically significant findings of any single team. What matters is the epidemiological study 0.20 1:10 0.30 Underpowered exploratory epidemiological study 0.12 0.20 1:1,000 0.80 Discovery-oriented exploratory 0.0010 http://www.plosmedicine.org/ PLoS Medicine | www.plosmedicine.org 0701 August 2005 | Volume 2 | Issue 8 | e124 totality of the evidence. Diminishing bias through enhanced research standards and curtailing of prejudices may also help. However, this may require a change in scientific mentality that might be difficult to achieve. In some research designs, efforts may also be more successful with upfront registration of studies, e.g., randomized trials [35]. Registration would pose a challenge for hypothesis- generating research. Some kind of registration or networking of data collections or investigators within fields may be more feasible than registration of each and every hypothesis- generating experiment. Regardless, even if we do not see a great deal of progress with registration of studies in other fields, the principles of developing and adhering to a protocol could be more widely borrowed from randomized controlled trials. Finally, instead of chasing statistical significance, we should improve our understanding of the range of R values—the pre-study odds—where research efforts operate [10]. Before running an experiment, investigators should consider what they believe the chances are that they are testing a true rather than a non-true relationship. Speculated high R values may sometimes then be ascertained. As described above, whenever ethically acceptable, large studies with minimal bias should be performed on research findings that are considered relatively established, to see how often they are indeed confirmed. I suspect several established “classics” will fail the test [36]. Nevertheless, most new discoveries will continue to stem from hypothesis- generating research with low or very low pre-study odds. We should then acknowledge that statistical significance testing in the report of a single study gives only a partial picture, without knowing how much testing has been done outside the report and in the relevant field at large. Despite a large statistical literature for multiple testing corrections [37], usually it is impossible to decipher how much data dredging by the reporting authors or other research teams has preceded a reported research finding. Even if determining this were feasible, this would not inform us about the pre-study odds. Thus, it is unavoidable that one should make approximate assumptions on how many relationships are expected to be true among those probed across the relevant research fields and research designs. The wider field may yield some guidance for estimating this probability for the isolated research project. Experiences from biases detected in other neighboring fields would also be useful to draw upon. Even though these assumptions would be considerably subjective, they would still be very useful in interpreting research claims and putting them in context. ■ References 1. Ioannidis JP, Haidich AB, Lau J (2001) Any casualties in the clash of randomised and observational evidence? BMJ 322: 879–880. 2. Lawlor DA, Davey Smith G, Kundu D, Bruckdorfer KR, Ebrahim S (2004) Those confounded vitamins: What can we learn from the differences between observational versus randomised trial evidence? Lancet 363: 1724– 1727. 3. Vandenbroucke JP (2004) When are observational studies as credible as randomised trials? Lancet 363: 1728–1731. 4. Michiels S, Koscielny S, Hill C (2005) Prediction of cancer outcome with microarrays: A multiple random validation strategy. Lancet 365: 488–492. 5. Ioannidis JPA, Ntzani EE, Trikalinos TA, Contopoulos-Ioannidis DG (2001) Replication validity of genetic association studies. Nat Genet 29: 306–309. 6. Colhoun HM, McKeigue PM, Davey Smith G (2003) Problems of reporting genetic associations with complex outcomes. Lancet 361: 865–872. 7. Ioannidis JP (2003) Genetic associations: False or true? Trends Mol Med 9: 135–138. 8. Ioannidis JPA (2005) Microarrays and molecular research: Noise discovery? Lancet 365: 454–455. 9. Sterne JA, Davey Smith G (2001) Sifting the evidence—What’s wrong with significance tests. BMJ 322: 226–231. 10. Wacholder S, Chanock S, Garcia-Closas M, El ghormli L, Rothman N (2004) Assessing the probability that a positive report is false: An approach for molecular epidemiology studies. J Natl Cancer Inst 96: 434–442. 11. Risch NJ (2000) Searching for genetic determinants in the new millennium. Nature 405: 847–856. 12. Kelsey JL, Whittemore AS, Evans AS, Thompson WD (1996) Methods in observational epidemiology, 2nd ed. New York: Oxford U Press. 432 p. 13. Topol EJ (2004) Failing the public health— Rofecoxib, Merck, and the FDA. N Engl J Med 351: 1707–1709. 14. Yusuf S, Collins R, Peto R (1984) Why do we need some large, simple randomized trials? Stat Med 3: 409–422. 15. Altman DG, Royston P (2000) What do we mean by validating a prognostic model? Stat Med 19: 453–473. 16. Taubes G (1995) Epidemiology faces its limits. Science 269: 164–169. 17. Golub TR, Slonim DK, Tamayo P, Huard C, Gaasenbeek M, et al. (1999) Molecular classification of cancer: Class discovery and class prediction by gene expression monitoring. Science 286: 531–537. 18. Moher D, Schulz KF, Altman DG (2001) The CONSORT statement: Revised recommendations for improving the quality of reports of parallel-group randomised trials. Lancet 357: 1191–1194. 19. Ioannidis JP, Evans SJ, Gotzsche PC, O’Neill RT, Altman DG, et al. (2004) Better reporting of harms in randomized trials: An extension of the CONSORT statement. Ann Intern Med 141: 781–788. 20. International Conference on Harmonisation E9 Expert Working Group (1999) ICH Harmonised Tripartite Guideline. Statistical principles for clinical trials. Stat Med 18: 1905– 1942. 21. Moher D, Cook DJ, Eastwood S, Olkin I, Rennie D, et al. (1999) Improving the quality of reports of meta-analyses of randomised controlled trials: The QUOROM statement. Quality of Reporting of Meta-analyses. Lancet 354: 1896–1900. 22. Stroup DF, Berlin JA, Morton SC, Olkin I, Williamson GD, et al. (2000) Meta-analysis of observational studies in epidemiology: A proposal for reporting. Meta-analysis of Observational Studies in Epidemiology (MOOSE) group. JAMA 283: 2008–2012. 23. Marshall M, Lockwood A, Bradley C, Adams C, Joy C, et al. (2000) Unpublished rating scales: A major source of bias in randomised controlled trials of treatments for schizophrenia. Br J Psychiatry 176: 249–252. 24. Altman DG, Goodman SN (1994) Transfer of technology from statistical journals to the biomedical literature. Past trends and future predictions. JAMA 272: 129–132. 25. Chan AW, Hrobjartsson A, Haahr MT, Gotzsche PC, Altman DG (2004) Empirical evidence for selective reporting of outcomes in randomized trials: Comparison of protocols to published articles. JAMA 291: 2457–2465. 26. Krimsky S, Rothenberg LS, Stott P, Kyle G (1998) Scientific journals and their authors’ financial interests: A pilot study. Psychother Psychosom 67: 194–201. 27. Papanikolaou GN, Baltogianni MS, Contopoulos-Ioannidis DG, Haidich AB, Giannakakis IA, et al. (2001) Reporting of conflicts of interest in guidelines of preventive and therapeutic interventions. BMC Med Res Methodol 1: 3. 28. Antman EM, Lau J, Kupelnick B, Mosteller F, Chalmers TC (1992) A comparison of results of meta-analyses of randomized control trials and recommendations of clinical experts. Treatments for myocardial infarction. JAMA 268: 240–248. 29. Ioannidis JP, Trikalinos TA (2005) Early extreme contradictory estimates may appear in published research: The Proteus phenomenon in molecular genetics research and randomized trials. J Clin Epidemiol 58: 543–549. 30. Ntzani EE, Ioannidis JP (2003) Predictive ability of DNA microarrays for cancer outcomes and correlates: An empirical assessment. Lancet 362: 1439–1444. 31. Ransohoff DF (2004) Rules of evidence for cancer molecular-marker discovery and validation. Nat Rev Cancer 4: 309–314. 32. Lindley DV (1957) A statistical paradox. Biometrika 44: 187–192. 33. Bartlett MS (1957) A comment on D.V. Lindley’s statistical paradox. Biometrika 44: 533–534. 34. Senn SJ (2001) Two cheers for P-values. J Epidemiol Biostat 6: 193–204. 35. De Angelis C, Drazen JM, Frizelle FA, Haug C, Hoey J, et al. (2004) Clinical trial registration: A statement from the International Committee of Medical Journal Editors. N Engl J Med 351: 1250–1251. 36. Ioannidis JPA (2005) Contradicted and initially stronger effects in highly cited clinical research. JAMA 294: 218–228. 37. Hsueh HM, Chen JJ, Kodell RL (2003) Comparison of methods for estimating the number of true null hypotheses in multiplicity testing. J Biopharm Stat 13: 675–689. http://www.plosmedicine.org/

PLACE THIS ORDER OR A SIMILAR ORDER WITH ONLINE NURSING PAPERS TODAY AND GET AN AMAZING DISCOUNT  ordernowcc-blue